Sunday, July 8, 2007

Responses to Quaker Philosophy Roundtable Queries

My responses to the Queries posed at the “Philosophers’ Roundtable” at the 2007 Annual Meetings of the Friends Association for Higher Education:


How do we see ourselves as scholars for peace, justice, or/and sustainability?

I will attempt to respond to this opening question “indirectly,” by means of responses to the subsequent questions, which I understand as sub-questions to this principal one, as ways of “getting at” this principal one. It would be both illusory and an impediment to “peace, justice, and sustainability” to think that we need to answer the following questions “first,” as if they were more abstract or foundational ones, before we could turn to this more practical one. Rather, we are as Quaker philosophers (or should be attempting to be, at least on my view) precisely scholars/philosophers for peace, justice and sustainability, and so the proper relationship between this first question and the subsequent ones is not that between an application and its theoretical bases, but that between end and means. Still, this relationship is complicated by the challenge of determining - even while being committed to them!, and perhaps above all for this reason - more exactly what peace, justice, and sustainability are and should be. And so the question that is perhaps rightly first in “religious priority” may not be the first we should attempt to answer, even if our responses to the subordinate questions cannot be adequate unless they are first of all (albeit necessarily incomplete) responses to this principal one, if at first only tacitly so.


What are we trying to accomplish in our teaching, our research, and our service?

I see my task as a teacher, broadly speaking, and as a teacher of philosophy in particular, as one of “encouraging cultivated imaginativity.” That is, I am of the conviction that “the world” (which is always the world in which we live and so includes us and our formative practices) is ever changing, and that each generation therefore faces challenges that the previous generations could not even have anticipated. (Analogies to already navigated waters can, of course, very often be found “after the fact,” so to speak, but to determine that a new situation is analogous to a foregoing one [and that it therefore calls for an already worked out solution, or some variation of it] itself requires a fresh judgment, and one that cannot presuppose the validity of the analogy.) My students will not only have to provide answers to new problems that I could not have taught them (the “answers” that I can teach them [even if “correct,” which is far from certain] may well not be answers to the questions that they will have to ask, and will almost certainly not be the answers that will fit the context in which they will be called upon to provide their answers), they will even have to ask questions that I could not have anticipated. In fact, I see it as one of the great disservices of dogmatic philosophy (and dogmatic theology, and dogmatic science) to put itself forth as providing, or even as seeking, timeless, “once and for all” answers that will not only be serviceable in every possible context, but will even, as universal, be an attempt to govern the parameters of any possible context. My task, then, cannot be to teach my students the right answers, for even if (miracle of miracles!) I could do so today, these answers would no longer be the right answers for tomorrow by dint of the changing questions. Or less radically (though for this perhaps so much the more subtle and the more commonly missed), the changing contexts in which the “same” questions need to be answered (those of a reputed philosophia perennis, for example) would effectively change the questions, and thus the required answers. I see it as my task then, to provide students with the broadest possible range of “tools” (in the loosest possible sense) for the imaginative work that lies ahead. I want to encourage an ever deepening plasticity and agility of mind (coupled with a perpetual questioning of the status quo), and philosophy is (historically, at least, and whatever else we might take it to be) a discipline (perhaps the paradigmatic one) that by its practice - if not always by its doctrine - is a model of the indefatigable variation of “takes” on things, of alternative paradigms, of the restless “reconstituting” of “the world” (i.e., of what we “best” take “the world” to “be,” and what we are to “do” about it - where all of these terms in scare quotes - and others - are precisely “in question,” i.e., yet to be determined). This is, whatever else it claims to be, at least rich fodder for the imagination. I take this (for rhetorical purposes, to be sure, but for more than that) to extremes in encouraging students “not to be intimidated too much my reality,” which is admittedly a peculiar charge coming from a philosopher. But I want students to genuinely believe that things do not have to be what they are, that (positive and radical) change is possible (tied to the Pauline claim that the me on is brought to humble and confound the on, that “what is not” is the necessary interruption and ultimately the redemption of “the powers that be [that are]”). And if this is not able to be transacted on the deepest levels (at the level of what is generally considered as the most real, at the level of what we generally take to be questions of ontology, or metaphysics, or cosmology), then the “changes” will correlatively never be anything other than ornamental. (Such that we might well get the change that, for a time at least, it will be lambs eating lions rather than lions eating lambs, but, unless the very structure of things is malleable, we’ll never get to the truly revolutionary: “lions lying down with the lambs” - which is a wonderful example of a marvelously imaginative, necessary, and true [“truer than true”] counter-factual.)

And yet, this “imaginativity,” so important on my view, cannot rest content with being an imaginativity “free like the wind,” cannot be confused a with mere fantasizing that abandons rather than transforms reality. (I am simultaneously committed to and want to question my own “cannot” in the forgoing statement. Who says we “cannot” rest content with mere fantasy? Backed up by what, or whom? But it is this “backed up by” that in each case I am suggesting we question, for it is this - and the fact that not only may we not question them, but that we cannot [reasonably] do so - upon which “the powers” rest.) And this is why it is essential to qualify this imaginativity with cultivation. We do not (it seems) get to start fresh, with a clean page, but inherit an already made world (but not for that immutable), one with which we need to seriously and soberly engage if our work of communal re-imagining is to be effective, and thus one it is essential that we understand as best we can. We awaken, spiritually and philosophically, already implicated in a history, in a history of struggle over “what is (to be) what”. Entering into this struggle is not only limiting, but also empowering. It is what we have been “given,” but it is not given as given once and for all - it comes with a call, a call to an ongoing responsibility.


What is philosophy?

My own sense is that philosophy is without an enduring essence; that philosophy, like everything else, is going to be for us largely what we make of it. Part of the task of each generation (school, type) of philosophers is to determine what philosophy is, i.e., what philosophy can and should responsibly be for its own time. And, indeed, perhaps the mark (or one of them) of a mature philosopher is a well worked out (and often idiosyncratic) version (although I would prefer here “vision”) of the nature of philosophy. (Never mind that in most cases this has been dressed up as the very essence of philosophy for all time, rather than as a responsible version for its time.) But this “responsibility” bespeaks a response; the discourse of philosophy is, qua discourse, a response to something beyond itself. We do not answer to our philosophies, we need to answer for our philosophies. Working out what it is that our philosophies answer to, trying to articulate “within” philosophy that which “precedes” in calling for philosophy, is one of the most interesting and perplexing problems of philosophy. What needs to be avoided is the “illusion” - created by the effort to articulate that to which philosophy is a response (and thus related to idolatry) - that that to which philosophy is a mere response becomes the “object” of philosophy, over which it then exercises a power. What we “have” within philosophy is a response, and not that to which it is a response (the call to philosophizing), we “have” the echo without the original sound, which leads to the illusion that it is philosophy that is, and that whatever else is going to be (to be taken as being) has to prove itself on philosophy’s terms. Thus the disasters of the famous “proofs for the existence of God,” “the criteria for meaningfulness” arising from logical positivism, even the prejudicing of “knowledge” over mere opinion, and an endless line of such pretensions.

There is therefore some cause for preferring to think of philosophy as “a way of life” rather than as a discipline with its subject matter, as a love of “wisdom,” but before “wisdom” is translated as “knowledge.” Philosophy needs be, on my view, an attentiveness to that to which it is a response, an “attentiveness” (an ongoing attending to, “hearing” of) precisely because none of its articulations of that to which it is a response are going to capture it. Philosophy is thus both a questioning (which gives it a certain power), and a being in question (which demands of it a deep humility) - charged to respond, to be responsible.


Is it the task of philosophy to connect with real world problems?

On my view, it is indeed the task of philosophy to engage in real world problems, and more than that, to transform them; that is, not only to participate in the clarification of the questions, and the formulation of responsible answers to our questions, but to assist (and perhaps even take the lead) in encouraging a re-visioning of the questions themselves (although this latter will of necessity be an “interdisciplinary” project [even if the tenets and outcomes of the very idea of disciplinarity are themselves questionable]). Put most radically: philosophy is not only charged to engage in real world problems, but to transform “the world” - to revision, to re-constitute, what “the world” itself is. (Mundane example, but for the sake of clarity: we might want to participate as philosophers in answering the question of how we can more justly distribute wealth, but we might also want to call into question the very mode of thinking whereby “wealth,” its meaning and value, is presupposed.) And that requires, at the same time, both the deepest engagement with the problems (the “cultivated” from above) and a supreme power of abstraction (the “imaginativity” from above). I cannot be “detached” or I’ll fail to understand the problem in its profundity and seriousness, and yet I cannot be so “engaged” that I cannot see a way “through,” or a way to reconfigure the field to allow for creativity and innovation. The “purely theoretical” aspect of philosophy is thus constitutive of its practicality, is one of the key moments in its applicability; philosophy must be “above it all” (but not in any moral [or extra-moral sense]) if it is to perform its function, but it cannot perform its function if it is merely or arrogantly “above it all.” The “abstract” nature of philosophy is thus not to be gainsaid by a too quick demand for relevance, but neither may it be an end in itself, or provide a justification for a smug and aloof sense of superiority.


Do we ever find our Quaker identity in conflict with our academic-philosophy identity, and if so, how do we respond to such conflicts?

This has never been a problem for me, but perhaps in part because of the way in which I conceive of philosophy.


Is there something that could be called “Quaker Philosophy”?

I am hesitant to think there is something that could be called “Quaker philosophy” if by that we were to think that we could translate “Quakerism” - a living religious practice - into a set of philosophical claims (against which I would have the same objections as I would against translating Quakerism into a set of theological claims).

I am more inclined to think that we should rather think of philosophizing in a Quakerly manner, but where the “way of engaging” in philosophical discourse is no mere add-on after the fact that would leave “philosophy” undisturbed at its core, but where the manner of philosophizing (e.g., in a Quakerly way) would affect (and sometimes even transform or effect, though not as a one-to-one correlation) the content of philosophy itself. (For this reason I think it ultimately inadequate for Quaker philosophers to be engaged only at the level of the adopting/adapting of philosophers that seem to resonate with, or at least not violate, Quaker notions, and avoiding those that do seem to contradict them). To philosophize peacefully, for example, neither presupposes nor guarantees any definitive philosophical content, but could hardly fail to give shape to whatever content it had at its disposal, or any content to which it would participate in giving shape.

So while the idea of a “Quaker philosophy” is not unproblematic, it is no more problematic than is the idea of philosophers who happen also to be Quakers (as if the latter were incidental to their philosophical practice), and so I generally prefer - at least in most contexts, and at least until persuaded otherwise - the former problematic term to the latter problematic one, as I prefer the designation “Quaker philosopher” to that of a “philosopher who is (i.e., just happens to be) a Quaker.”


Do Quakers have anything distinctive to offer to academic philosophy?

I trust this is the case, and am - buoyed and inspired by (and in gratitude for) the strong precedents established by Quaker philosophers in the twentieth century - anxious (and committed) to participate in discovering what we, as Quaker philosophers, might have to contribute in the twenty-first. Of course, such offerings are already being made by various individuals in a range of philosophical areas and schools, and I think it essential that we encourage and support each other, and learn from each other, even (and perhaps particularly) when we don’t agree with one another. But I wonder too whether there is not a contribution that we are called to make as a community of Quakers in philosophy, with the particular and peculiar set of sensibilities and insights and responsibilities with which we have been gifted. I am excited at the prospect of being a participant in an ongoing process of determining what this “distinctive offering” might be, and am hopeful that our “philosophers’ roundtable” at FAHE at Earlham College, and the discussions following up on it, may be an opening upon such an “opening.”

Jeffrey Dudiak, Associate Professor of Philosophy
The King’s University College, Edmonton, Alberta

7 comments:

forrest said...

Phew!

In studying math, you find many books with problems to be worked and answers in the back. One object is to be able to work the problems; so people say the answers are there as a check on whether the student is doing that correctly. That is the usefulness of those answers. But the ultimate object, as I see it, is to better grasp and contemplate the structure in which those problems and methods fit.

Philosophy may be even more like that; there are are standard problems (with suggested, rather than "correct" answers) and methods to be applied on them; even the study of such methods (Logic would be an example) gets included. But the best goal may well be, not so much learning of applicable methods but more a sense of how things "work" and "fit together" on a very abstract level.

A very metaphorical level, I might say. As a poet, I think we're in the same business. We throw a net of concepts and metaphors over the reality we swim in... (and if we catch ourselves?) Poetry, if it's done right, also demands a sort of precision, even if it doesn't need to be so neatly wrapped. Looking at things poetically, you find paradox sometimes more meaningful than any consistent description of things, as in "Everything is perfect, but some things could use a little improvement." But that doesn't mean one can just get sloppy, as if any old paradox could cure us. One must rant with precision!

You know, what you say about conflicting identities... So far as you are a Quaker, that's your job: to listen for and follow the Word of the Lord to you. Your identity as a philospher defines you in a different sense, like being a bird or a fish or a lover of science fiction. You don't really get a choice of being a Quaker or not--or a choice of being a philosopher or not (There's a distinction I'm having trouble grasping here!) Being a philosopher is more like being left-handed; it would affect how you approached anything you may do, but wouldn't lay any particular task on you. Being a Quaker might...

So maybe there's a philosophical term for these two different sorts of identity? Both are roles, both pretty close to what the old guys would have called our individual "essence"... Your philosophical studies might conceivably flip your world into some whole new gestalt; but sitting in your folding chair (or bench?) at meeting, that could make an even greater difference... One is about how you think of It All, and the other can bring you up against the way It All thinks of you.

RichardM said...

Jeff,

You had a lot to say in your answers to the prompts. I'll respond to just one of them for now.

Are there perennial issues that philosophers should respond to or does human experience change so much that there are no perennial issues?

Obviously there is both change and continuity in human history. Does philosophy arise primarily from what changes or from what doesn't?

Take death as an example. Our average lifespan has increased. Sudden death has gotten significantly rarer. That's change. But the maximum age we can expect to live hasn't changed. Our bodies start to seriously deteriorate at "three score and ten" as they always have. The fact of mortality hasn't changed. Does this raise issues for thoughtful human beings? I'd say death is one of those perennial issues little affected by cultural or historical change.

Another example is limits on resources available to human beings. The issue of distributive justice arises because the things that humans want are not unlimited. So questions about who gets what share of the limited resources make thoughtful human beings ask what a just society would look like. If we would ever "return to Eden" and have all our wants fulfilled by an abundance that outran human desire then questions of distributive justive would become moot. Times have changed. We can produce more now. Compared to what our ancestors knew our society does produce a fantastic abundance. But it is still limited. There are still arguments over how much any individual deserves. Distributive Justice is a perennial issue.

I could go on in the same vein of course. Human fallibility raises perennial questions about knowledge. Our love of beauty raises questions about art. But the other side of the coin cries out for expression. Where has 25 centures of discussion of these perennial issues gotten us? Are we getting anywhere? If not, shouldn't we seek something new?

The radical philosopher who is frustrated by perennial philosophy speaks to my condition as well. The creative response, as I see it, is not to throw out the old problems and seek new problems. The creative response is to forge new conceptual tools for dealing with the old problems. In a sense this does reshape the old problems. For example if I propose a new concept of knowledge then the "problem of knowledge" automatically becomes a different (even if only slightly different) problem.

This is why I argue for the conceptualistic pragmatism of C.I. Lewis. It's all about creating new and more useful concepts.

forrest said...

Like Confucious: "reforming" the language? Or like poets, rewarping and prehaps deforming it?

I like the way Raymond Smullyan (a logician, as I should expect) tends to put questions in terms of how he likes to look at things.

That might sound too much like discarding the basic Truth Test--but I see it as closer to the way a mathematician will seek more fruitful ways to formulate or visualize a problem.

ie, The traditional proof of the Pythagorian Theorem is complex and doesn't make much intuitive sense--But there's a drawing that makes it perfectly obvious. Two ways to draw an (x+y) by (x+y) square, with 4 x-by-y right triangles inside, filling the same amount of space inside, leaving:

(drawing 'a') two squares, x^2 and y^2 -- or (drawing 'b') one square formed by the four ["hypotenooses"? Arrgh! I look it up: "Currently, the plural of hypotenuse is hypotenuses. Perhaps cooler substitutes should be hypotenusage, hypotenii, or hypoteneese."] hypotenuses.

New ways to conceive of a problem can make all the difference, whether it's going to be intractible or obvious...

Jeffrey Dudiak said...

Richard,

Thank you for your opening comment on my remarks. For me, the question is whether the “perennial” issues in philosophy (allowing for the moment that there have been such) are a function of a nature that imposes them upon us, or whether they are the result of our having not yet imagined an alternative way of conceiving of things. Put otherwise, is “truth” best defined as “the way things (necessarily) are,” or, alternatively (and as I have been entertaining of late), as “a lack of imagination”?

I do not believe that there is an “in principle” way of adjudicating between the foregoing “options” (or even of establishing, moreover, the necessity of this either/or itself). Philosophy (and science, and philosophy as scientia), has predominantly opted for the former (and has even attempted to argue that the belief in such a forced choice is itself a forced choice); I am advocating at least a serious flirtation with the latter.

And so, I think we are not so far from one another when you write: “The creative response, as I see it, is not to throw out the old problems and seek new problems. The creative response is to forge new conceptual tools for dealing with the old problems. In a sense this does reshape the old problems.” My suspicion, however, is that I believe in the possibility of a more radical reshaping than do you. My sense is that we do well to “perennially” test and push the limits of this reshaping (that is, on my view, the true philosophia perennis), that that is at least a large part of our critical/philosophical task: questioning anyone who tells us that something has to be the way that it is.

I would want to add, however, that this “radicality” in philosophy is not for its own sake. Philosophy, on my view (which like everything else should be questioned; as should the claim that “everything should be questioned” itself), is “in the service of” the abundant life to which we are called by God, and should be more or less radical as that service demands. It is my judgment that the times demand of us a “radical” philosophizing, but that is a discussion that we would need to have.

Jeffrey Dudiak

L. J. Rediehs said...

Thank you, Jeffrey, for sharing your thoughts on these questions! There is a lot that I resonate with in what you say. And I like the way you put things: "cultivated imaginativity," "agility of mind," for example. I very much appreciate your emphasis on the ways that philosophy can (and does) help in transforming the world, in large part by helping us to think about things in new ways. New thinking must precede any real change.

And I also appreciate your thoughts on the connection between being a Quaker and being a philosopher. I too feel inclined to something more than just thinking of myself as a philosopher who happens to be Quaker (or a Quaker who happens to be a philosopher, for that matter!) The connection between these two in my own soul feels stronger than that. And for this reason too, I really resonate with what you say in your last paragraph.

Your hesitancy to define philosophy intrigues me. I understand why, and am sympathetic with the reasons. And, yet, I worry sometimes about how philosophers' reluctance to give a clear answer to the question "what is philosophy?" (and Quakers' reluctance to give a clear answer to "what is Quakerism?") can foster confusion and misunderstanding, making both seem intimidatingly unapproachable to people who might in fact benefit from engagement with them.

I think your answer to the question is a good one in a conversation among other philosophers. But what do you say to those new to philosophy? What do others say? (What do I say?) What would be good to say?

Craig Dove said...

I appreciate the idea of philosophy as an ongoing conversation, to be redefined as we go; however, I'm not entirely sure that it is "without an enduring essence," even though I don't typically go in for essentialist thinking. Even as a way of life, it seems that there is something that connects what I'm doing with what Socrates is doing, even if "that" is radically shaped by the needs of the context. The notions of attentiveness and responsiveness, to say nothing of responsibility, offer an interesting starting point, but I'm not sure that it adequately distinguishes philosophy from (and this is coming out of my context) pastoral care.
That said, I like the interpretation of the Socratic dialogues that I've recently stumbled across again: that the aporias in those dialogues aren't simply dead-ends, but an invitation to move the conversation outside the text, that the text cannot contain the answers we're looking for. That has to be part of a way of life, and the questions have to be conditioned (if not determined) by our milieu; but I think there's still something about the way in which we respond, what counts as a legitimate response, that helps to define philosophy a bit more narrowly.

Jeffrey Dudiak said...

Thank you, Laura and Craig, for continuing this conversation. (Let’s hope others too are drawn in, and feel welcome to participate!) Even though I am beginning to feel the impediments to saying quite what I would like to say imposed by the “blog” format (I find myself sounding more sure about things than I really am), I’m grateful for this chance to continue conversations begun elsewhere, leading perhaps to more thorough future encounters.

I should clarify, Laura, that I am not against defining philosophy; on the contrary, my sense is that defining philosophy is one of our most important philosophical tasks, one that will play a large part in determining what our philosophizing is “good for” (if anything). But it is, on my view, precisely a task, a responsibility. And this because philosophy, like every other discourse, is spoken “to” someone - is already a response. So a discourse always has its “center,” its “focus,” outside of itself in those to whom it is an attempt to respond. (I wonder whether this does not connect with Craig’s second paragraph above.) So we cannot and should not avoid defining philosophy; we must define it - ever and again, but not forever and always - because the exigencies to which we are called to respond vary across time and place, and present us with a “moving target.” Without that sense of those to whom philosophy answers, philosophy is as susceptible to dogmatism as is theology, or science, or any discourse. So I certainly define philosophy for my beginning students (and your suggestions [from your Sept. 4 post] of philosophy as wisdom, and/or philosophy as negotiating an is/ought dialectic, are viable starting points - and perhaps as viable as any), but as an invitation to a world of questioning before as a presentation of answers or even as a way to provide them - yet as an invitation not to questioning willy-nilly (for the sake of questioning), but as an attempt to ask “good” (i.e., responsive, responsible) questions, even about philosophy itself. (How well I actually do this is another question, of course. I’m sure I often fail. But those of us attempting to teach philosophy know well the obstacles and the pitfalls.)

Craig’s concern that, even granted the above (which he might or might not grant - I won’t speak for him), there is surely nevertheless something that distinguishes philosophy from other discourses (his e.g. is “pastoral care”), and his intuition that there is “something that connects what I am doing to what Socrates is doing,” seems to suggest that that “something” is, somehow, of the essence of philosophy, or something like an essence. Of course, defining what that “something” is is difficult indeed, especially when the problem becomes identifying not only what “connects what I am doing to what Socrates is doing” but “connects what I am doing to the doings of Socrates, and Plato, and Epicurus, and Plotinus, and Anselm, and Pico, and Rousseau, and Fichte, and Sartre, and Ayer.” But the fact that we mention all of these together despite the difficulty of identifying a shared method or matter, does suggest that they share “something.” Whether there is an “essence” to philosophy that each philosopher aims at (and that each participates in in a limited way), or whether “philosophy” is rather simply the name for a series of loosely associated and contingent discourses that have more of an historical than “essential” connection, is a question that I do not believe can be decided in principle. (I prefer the latter position, one that denies that philosophy has an “an sich” character, that denies therefore that philosophy is built into the necessary structure of things, and thus has an inherent right “to be” [and to be what it “is” independent of other concerns, or concern for the/its “other”], partly because of my incredulity toward arguments for the former position, but mostly because I think that philosophy [like every discourse] should have to answer for itself.) But in either case, if we are to enter into the philosophical enterprise as an at least potentially fruitful undertaking (and why else would we enter into it?), it would appear to be among our obligations to “define” philosophy such that its fruits could be borne. The defining of those fruits and of the methods of their cultivation seems to me not to be given with philosophy, but remains among its tasks. The defining of the above mentioned “something” falls upon us, each new generation, and each community, of philosophers. In short, my sense is that as philosophers, we are responsible not “to” philosophy, but “for” it.

Jeff Dudiak